Epistemology is the branch of philosophy
that studies knowledge. It attempts to answer the basic question: what
distinguishes true (adequate) knowledge
from false (inadequate) knowledge? Practically, this questions translates
into issues of scientific methodology: how can one develop theories or
models that are better than competing theories? It also forms one of the
pillars of the new sciences of cognition, which developed from the information
processing approach to psychology, and from artificial intelligence, as
an attempt to develop computer programs that mimic a human's capacity to
use knowledge in an intelligent way.
When we look at the history of epistemology, we
can discern a clear trend, in spite of the confusion of many seemingly
contradictory positions. The first theories of knowledge stressed its absolute,
permanent character, whereas the later theories put the emphasis on its
relativity or situation-dependence, its continuous development or evolution,
and its active interference with the world and its subjects and objects.
The whole trend moves from a static, passive view of knowledge towards
a more and more adaptive and active one.
Let us start with the Greek philosophers. In Plato's
view knowledge is merely an awareness of absolute, universal Ideas
or Forms, existing independent of any subject trying to apprehend
to them. Though Aristotle puts more emphasis on logical and empirical methods
for gathering knowledge, he still accepts the view that such knowledge
is an apprehension of necessary and universal principles. Following the
Renaissance, two main epistemological positions dominated philosophy: empiricism,
which sees knowledge as the product of sensory perception, and rationalism
which sees it as the product of rational reflection.
The implementation of empiricism in the newly developed
experimental sciences led to a view of knowledge which is still explicitly
or implicity held by many people nowadays: the reflection-correspondence
theory. According to this view knowledge results from a kind of mapping
or reflection of external objects, through our sensory organs, possibly
aided by different observation instruments, to our brain or mind. Though
knowledge has no a priori existence, like in Plato's conception, but has
to be developed by observation, it is still absolute, in the sense that
any piece of proposed knowledge is supposed to either truly correspond
to a part of external reality, or not. In that view, we may in practice
never reach complete or absolute knowledge, but such knowledge is somehow
conceivable as a limit of ever more precise reflections of reality.
The following important theory developed in that period
is the Kantian synthesis of rationalism and empiricism. According
to Kant, knowledge results from the organization of perceptual data on
the basis of inborn cognitive structures, which he calls "categories".
Categories include space, time, objects and causality. This epistemology
does accept the subjectivity of basic concepts, like space and time, and
the impossibility to reach purely objective representations of things-in-themselves.
Yet the a priori categories are still static or given.
The next stage of development of epistemology may
be called pragmatic. Parts of it can be found in early twentieth
century approaches, such as logical positivism, conventionalism, and the
"Copenhagen interpretation" of quantum mechanics. This philosophy still
dominates most present work in cognitive science and artificial intelligence.
According to pragmatic epistemology, knowledge consists of models
that attempt to represent the environment in such a way as to maximally
simplify problem-solving.
It is assumed that no model can ever hope to capture all relevant information,
and even if such a complete model would exist, it would be too complicated
to use in any practical way. Therefore we must accept the parallel existence
of different models, even though they may seem contradictory. The model
which is to be chosen depends on the problems that are to be solved. The
basic criterion is that the model should produce correct (or approximate)
predictions (which may be tested) or problem-solutions, and be as simple
as possible. Further questions about the "Ding an Sich" or ultimate reality
behind the model are meaningless.
The pragmatic epistemology does not give a clear answer
to the question where knowledge or models come from. There is an implicit
assumption that models are built from parts of other models and empirical
data on the basis of trial-and-error
complemented with some heuristics or intuition. A more radical point of
departure is offered by constructivism.
It assumes that all knowledge is built up from scratch by the subject of
knowledge. There are no 'givens', neither objective empirical data or facts,
nor inborn categories or cognitive structures. The idea of a correspondence
or reflection of external reality is rejected. Because of this lacking
connection between models and the things they represent, the danger with
constructivism is that it may lead to relativism, to the idea that any
model constructed by a subject is as good as any other and that there is
no way to distinguish adequate or 'true' knowledge from inadequate or 'false'
knowledge.
We can distinguish two approaches trying to avoid such
an 'absolute relativism'. The first may be called individual constructivism.
It assumes that an individual attempts to reach coherence
among the different pieces of knowledge. Constructions that are inconsistent
with the bulk of other knowledge that the individual has will tend to be
rejected. Constructions that succeed in integrating previously incoherent
pieces of knowledge will be maintained. The second, to be called social
constructivism, sees consensus between different subjects as the ultimate
criterion to judge knowledge. 'Truth' or 'reality' will be accorded only
to those constructions on which most people of a social group agree.
In these philosophies, knowledge is seen as largely independent
of a hypothetical 'external reality' or environment. As the 'radical' constructivists
Maturana
and
Varela argue,
the nervous system of an organism cannot in any absolute way distinguish
between a perception (caused by an external phenomenon) and a hallucination
(a purely internal event). The only basic criterion is that different mental
entities or processes within or between individuals should reach some kind
of equilibrium.
Though these constructivistic approaches put much
more emphasis on the changing and relative character of knowledge, they
are still absolutist in the primacy they give to either social consensus
or internal coherence, and their description of construction processes
is quite vague and incomplete. A more broad or synthetic outlook is offered
by different forms or evolutionary
epistemology. Here it is assumed that knowledge is constructed by the
subject or group of subjects in order to adapt to their environment in
the broad sense. That construction is an on-going process at different
levels, biological as well as psychological or social. Construction happens
through blind variation
of existing pieces of knowledge, and the selective retention of those new
combinations that somehow contribute most to the survival and reproduction
of the subject(s) within their given environment. Hence we see that the
'external world' again enters the picture, although no objective reflection
or correspondence is assumed, only an equilibrium between the products
of internal variation and different (internal or external) selection criteria.
Any form of absolutism or permanence has disappeared in this approach,
but knowledge is basically still a passive instrument developed by organisms
in order to help them in their quest for survival.
A most recent, and perhaps most radical approach, extends
this evolutionary view in order to make knowledge actively pursue goals
of its own. This approach, which as yet has not had the time to develop
a proper epistemology, may be called memetics.
It notes that knowledge can be transmitted from one subject to another,
and thereby loses its dependence on any single individual. A piece of knowledge
that can be transmitted or replicated in such a way is called a 'meme'.
The death of an individual carrying a certain meme now no longer implies
the elimination of that piece of knowledge, as evolutionary epistemology
would assume. As long as a meme spreads more quickly to new carriers, than
that its carriers die, the meme will proliferate, even though the knowledge
it induces in any individual carrier may be wholly inadequate and even
dangerous to survival. In this view a piece of knowledge may be succesful
(in the sense that it is common or has many carriers) even though its predictions
may be totally wrong, as long as it is sufficiently 'convincing' to new
carriers. Here we see a picture where even the subject of knowledge has
lost his primacy, and knowledge becomes a force of its own with proper
goals and ways of developing itself. That this is realistic can be illustrated
by the many superstitions, fads, and irrational beliefs that have spread
over the globe, sometimes with a frightening speed.
Like social constructivism, memetics attracts the attention
to communication and social processes in the development of knowledge,
but instead of seeing knowledge as constructed by the social system, it
rather sees social systems as constructed by knowledge processes. Indeed,
a social group can be defined by the fact that all its members share the
same meme (Heylighen, 1992). Even the concept of 'self', that which distinguishes
a person as a individual, can be considered as a piece of knowledge, constructed
through social processes (Harr*, 19), and hence a result of memetic evolution.
From a constructivist approach, where knowledge is constructed by individuals
or society, we have moved to a memetic approach, which sees society and
even individuality as byproducts constructed by an ongoing evolution of
independent fragments of knowledge competing for domination.
We have come very far indeed from Plato's immutable and
absolute Ideas, residing in an abstract realm far from concrete objects
or subjects, or from the naive realism of the reflection-correspondence
theory, where knowledge is merely an image of external objects and their
relations. At this stage, the temptation would be strong to lapse into
a purely anarchistic or relativistic attitude, stating that 'anything goes',
and that it would be impossible to formulate any reliable and general criteria
to distinguish 'good' or adequate pieces of knowledge from bad or inadequate
ones. Yet in most practical situations, our intuition does help us to distinguish
perceptions from dreams or hallucinations, and unreliable predictions ('I
am going to win the lottery') from reliable ones ('The sun will come up
tomorrow morning'). And an evolutionary
theory still assumes a natural selection
which can be understood to a certain degree. Hence we may assume that it
is possible to identify selection criteria, but one of the lessons of this
historical overview will be that we should avoid to quickly formulate one
absolute criterion. Neither correspondence, nor coherence or consensus,
and not even survivability, are sufficient to ground a theory of knowledge.
At this stage we can only hope to find multiple, independent, and sometimes
contradictory criteria,
whose judgment may quickly become obsolete. Yet if we would succeed to
formulate these criteria clearly, within a simple and general conceptual
framework, we would have an epistemology that synthesizes and extends al
of the traditional and less traditional philosophies above.